The Standards for Mathematical Practice (SMP) are often cited as evidence that the current math content standards suggest a significant shift in mathematics education. This shift is frequently framed as a more holistic or progressive view of math education because the SMP capture the more enduring capacities and dispositions students should develop in math class. In other words, they purportedly paint a fuller picture about what it means to do math, or put differently, what it is that mathematicians do.
Yet, reading the SMP in their entirety it is difficult not to conjure up the stereotypical image of the lone mathematician wrangling with abstractions, obsessed with precision and structure, and quick to criticism. It is the mathematics of an elite few who can persevere. It is not a portrait of mathematics that is necessarily new, appealing, or even accurate.
In Living Mathematx: Towards a Vision for the Future, Dr. Rochelle Gutiérrez draws a contrast between “critiquing the reasoning of others” and “appreciating the reasoning of others” (Gutiérrez, 2017). This contrast inspired me to wonder more deeply about the completeness of the SMP whether a similar siblingship can be found for each practice.
This is not to say that the practices in the SMP are not important in mathematics – just that they are not the totality of mathematics. They are incomplete. And not only in the sense that they are not an exhaustive list of mathematical practices (though certainly that is true too), but also in the sense that each practice is itself incomplete. It only paints with half the color needed to capture the full vibrancy of mathematics.
Building off of Gutiérrez’s inspiration in Living Mathematx, I believe a complementing practice does exist for each SMP – a practice that is opposite (or nearly opposite), though not necessarily oppositional, and equally mathematical. Click each practice for additional explanation:
1. Make sense of problems and persevere in solving them /
Pose questions, pursue joy, and embrace mystery
SMP.1 encapsulates three distinct practices: problem solving, sense making, and perseverance. Accordingly, each is paired with its own complement.
First, SMP.1 frames the work of mathematics as addressing pre-formed and prescribed problems. But mathematicians also pose their own questions and make their own problems. Mathematicians are constantly asking, “What if?” Cardano and Bombelli wondered if the square roots of negatives could be used in arithmetic just like integers and the foundation for complex numbers emerged. Ada Lovelace wondered what else an Analytical Engine might do and was the first to imagine possibilities for computers beyond the realm of mathematical calculation. Von Neumann and Morgenstern asked if mathematics could help us understand games, economics, and strategic thinking. Mathematicians are constantly dreaming, wondering, and posing new questions.
These questions are not pursued just as an exercise in endurance. Mathematics can be joyful and exhilarating. Francis Su asserts that the basic human desire for play is deeply connected to the practice of mathematics. While many mathematicians find the appeal of math to be in its thrill and beauty, SMP.1 highlights a sense of difficulty and hardship – a math that must be persevered. Developing persistence is good, but not necessarily for its own sake and certainly not as a gatekeeper. Finding joy can feed the desire to persist. Finding joy is also worthy on its own.
Joy in math is also not always found in solutions or answers. Math is teeming with confounding ideas whose power cannot be fully grasped without an appreciation their mystery. The Banach-Tarski Paradox shows how a single ball can be disassembled and then re-assembled into two balls that are identical copies of the first. Cantor’s revelation that there is more than one size of infinity baffled even his most notable contemporaries. Mathematics has more meaning when we are able to hold both how something can seem not to be and also how it is. Additionally, like Cantor’s detractors, math is not always understood the first time around, or the second, or third. Feeling a sense of mystery, confusion, and uncertainty is a normal and necessary part of mathematics.
2. Reason abstractly and quantitatively / Math is more than a cold and distant logic described with numbers. Mathematics can be done with and about very real and tangible objects. Mathematics can also involve working with space and shapes, from basic to advanced geometry to three-dimensional calculus. Shapes and spaces can be assembled, dissected, and transformed. The spatial is just as mathematical as the numerical. Mathematicians also use their intuition and gut. William Byers writes that a mathematician can often feel or sense that “something is going on here” before they delve in the logic of it.1 Mathematicians might feel that something does not sit right before fully being able to articulate a flaw in an argument. Or, they might have a gut instinct of a strategy to try. Mathematicians also decide which of the many unsolved problems and unasked questions to pursue and which direction to go with them. Perhaps informed by evidence and experience, their choice is nevertheless into some degree of the unknown. Byers also writes, “math research is characterized by an instinct for the right problems: those that are significant yet accessible [italics added].”1 3. Construct viable arguments and critique the reasoning of others / The history of mathematics is full of people who made great contributions but who also held wrong convictions. Pythagoras has the perhaps apocryphal legend of refusing to acknowledge the existence of irrational numbers and then having someone killed when they dared to argue otherwise. Less apocryphally, Hilbert spent over a decade of work and argument on his program to create formalized and axiomatic mathematics. Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorem, however, would show that Hilbert’s vision was not possible. And yet even though Hilbert’s arguments proved inviable, was he not still was practicing and contributing to mathematics? Mathematicians often pursue ideas that do not work out or are later found to be incorrect or incomplete. Moreover, even correct and viable ideas are often only last in a long line of failed attempts. Proposing incorrect, incomplete, and inviable arguments and ideas is an as common, if not more common, occurrence than posing correct, complete, and viable ones. And yet each incomplete, incorrect, inviable attempt still develops the field of mathematics. Accepting their fallibility and limited perspective requires mathematicians to approach their work with humility. Appreciating the reasoning of others (originally coined by Gutierrez, 2017) not only expands our own thinking but also enlarges the possibilities for mathematics itself. Unfortunately, the history of math more easily illustrates this truth in counterexample. Many Europeans initially refused to accept the concept of zero already use in India and many other places (see here and here). As mentioned above, Cantor’s ideas about infinity where initially resisted by his peers. Math has the potential to be so much richer when we are truly open to understanding other ways of thinking, seeing, and doing. And, perhaps more importantly, our treatment of people and cultivation of our collective humanity is enriched when we seek to first understand and appreciate others. 4. Model with mathematics / SMP.4 frames mathematical modeling as a non-invasive act of an outside observer. Yet, mathematics and mathematical models have had real and sometimes deleterious effects on people. Cathy O’Neil has documented how mathematical models have facilitated the mistreatment of workers, helped determine who gets policed, affected hiring practices, and contributed to the widening wealth gap.3 Mathematics should not be practiced under the assumption that the work is abstract and without tangible and human consequence. It is not just used to understand the world; it also affects the world. Ethical and moral mathematicians take responsibility and ownership for the impact their work and their field has on people. This includes taking action to correct and prevent harm and oppression. For example, a group of mathematicians recently called for their colleagues to stop work on predictive policing and other algorithms that have perpetuated racism and police brutality. This practice cannot be fully realized unless the diversity of mathematicians and mathematical practices reflects the diversity of our world and community. Thus, this practice also requires mathematicians to actively broaden both the mathematical community and the practice of math itself. 5. Use appropriate tools strategically / Mathematicians regularly develop tools to meet their needs. Today, the coordinate grid might be considered a useful tool in certain situations. But for Rene Descartes it was a new idea. And so he developed the now common tool for identifying location. The development of mathematical tools did not stop hundreds of years ago – it continues today. In the 1930s, Mary Clem invented the Zero Check method to detect errors. Even as recently as 2019, a new method was developed for solving a quadratic equation. Mathematicians also use tools in ways that they were not necessarily intended. In doing so they often reveal useful and even unexpected connections. Trigonometric functions, Exponential functions, and complex numbers seem like distinct tools for understanding different phenomena. But they find a surprising connection in Euler’s Formula. The arithmetic of complex numbers was also found to model geometric rotations. Galois used groups to draw conclusions about the solutions polynomial equations. Groups then became a study unto themselves and now appear in multiple fields of mathematics. Integration as a tool for finding area and differentiation as a tool for finding velocity are bound together in the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus. Mathematicians practice creativity including finding new applications for and insightful connections between mathematical tools. 6. Attend to precision / It can often be useful to ignore or flaunt precision. Scientific notation of course rounds off the digits that have little meaning in the context of very large and very small numbers. In geometry, imperfect diagrams are drawn that do not attend to scale, congruence, or angle measure. Interpreting what is rigid and what has flexibility in these diagrams is a skill in and of itself. In calculus, functions are graphed with a few key points connected by a rough curve. More generally, many problems are first tackled with slapdash sketch. And, of course, estimation often requires forgoing precision in favor of rough approximation. Abandoning precision can facilitate understanding, highlight important features, and simplify complex work. It could be argued that ‘attending to precision’ includes also knowing when to ignore precision. In a denotative sense this may be true, but the title and description of SMP.6 clearly intends to emphasize detail, accuracy, and specificity over the practices described above. 7. Look for and make use of structure / Mathematicians find new ideas by questioning or ignoring aspects of previous defined structure. Euclid found a structure for a geometry built on five postulates. Then mathematicians negated his 5th postulate and opened the door to multiple non-Euclidian geometries. In a similar sense, the study of topology finds no difference between the shape of a coffee cup and a donut or the shape of an ellipse and a circle, thus abandoning many of the geometric and physical structures normally associated with those shapes. Consider also that the study of statistics depends on the notion of randomness, a complete lack of structure. Of course, some might argue that randomness has structure. Thus, in the sense, the word structure is taken to encompass both itself and its opposite. SMP.7, however, does not attempt to define structure in such a broad sense. SMP.7 defines the practice of mathematics as strictly about looking for order and organization. SMP.7 does not position mathematicians as having the freedom to wonder what happens when certain aspects of order and organization are ignored. It does not describe structure as something made or defined, only found. Moreover, the existence of structure in one area inherently implies the lack of structure elsewhere. How can structure be noticed or defined other than as a boundary, or distinction, between itself and the thing it is not? Thus, the ‘thing it is not’ must also exist and is an interesting and valid mathematical consideration. 8. Look for and express regularity in repeated reasoning / Mathematics is not just about pattern and repetition. Mathematicians also notice what is unique. For instance, the defining features of a shape or function that make it distinct and different. Mathematicians do not just develop rules to demonstrate expectations – they also find exceptions. The discovery of single counterexample can disprove a generalized conjecture. The search for uniqueness also produces interesting results. There are only five Platonic solids. There are only 17 wallpaper groups. Consider also that Fermat’s Last Theorem asserted that that integer solutions to an + bn = cn only exists when n=1 or 2. The generalization that no solutions exists for n>2 is inextricable from the special cases where solutions do exist. Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic exemplifies this tension between the value of the unique and the expectation of pattern, repetition, and generalization. Every integer is either prime or can be represented by a unique product of primes. What is more essential to this insight: the regularity that this property holds from one integer to the next or the uniqueness of the set of prime factors? Both Always There is a temptation to view the pairs of a practices above in a strict dichotomy. Thus, provoking an argument over which side is the most important, essential, or truest to the nature of mathematical practice. But the framing of these complementing pairs does not have to be either/or. Consider how folk-singer Ani DiFranco challenges the binary conceptualization of gender in her memoir:4 Nature’s math seems to me to be possessed of a profoundly simple grace: 1 = 0 2 = ∞ As in: There really is no such thing as a singularity (a thing operating outside of a relationship) and two is always the springboard to infinity…. When you think of binary in terms of a relationship instead of the number, it becomes not about either/or but about both always. It’s about a world in dialog with itself…Binary systems in nature are in motion. They are fluid and spinning and overlapping and interconnected and, from moment to moment, they evolve. The complementing practices above are the two that gives the springboard to infinity. Not an either/or but a both always. There is harmony in DiFranco’s words and Byers description of the tension between logic and ambiguity in mathematics. “Mathematics,” he writes, “moves back and forth between these two poles. Mathematics is not a fixed, static, entity that can be structured definitely. It is dynamic, alive: its dynamism the function of the relationship between the two poles…”1 This attempt to avoid an either/or framing can also be understood through the lens of Nepantla, an Indigenous concept identified by Gutiérrez as one of the guiding principals for developing a Living Mathematx (2017). As she writes, “It means being willing to hold two or more contradictory views in one’s mind at the same time with the goal of not quickly coming to a conclusion that subsumes both ideas under an umbrella but maintains some of those views and reaches a third space that is neither and both of those views” (2017). On their own the SMP paint a less-than-half picture of mathematical practice. Consider how in one sense blue is half of green. But there also is something unaccounted for in that division. And something more appears in the exchange between blue and yellow than the sum of two halves. Not to mention the many possible greens that can arise in a spinning mix of blues and yellows. In that same spirit, the eight complements above should also not be interpreted as completely encapsulating the practice of mathematics. The vast majority of the mathematicians cited in the examples above are European and male. This is partially an intentional decision to illustrate how the SMP fail to fully capture the nature of even this narrow band of mathematics. It is also partially a product of the biases that were present in my own education. Yet, it is also indicative of another incompleteness. A consideration of a wider spectrum and history of mathematical practice would undoubtedly produce additional complementing pairs of practice. There is certainly a ninth pair, and tenth, and so on. It is often quipped that, “math is what mathematicians do.” Yet oppressive and exclusionary structures have limited and continue to limit who gets to do math and whose math counts. Overemphasis on an SMP style of math in our pedagogy, policy, power structures, and culture has certainly contributed to this oppression and exclusion. The actual mathematics enacted and permitted in schools has generally not reflected the “both always”, fluid, and dynamic theory described above. The one-sided approach of the SMP imbues in learners a false and incomplete view of mathematics. Worse, it perpetuates forces of exclusion and oppression. Thus, while theory eschews the either/or frame, the enacted mathematics in schools requires a corrective balancing. Pedagogy and policy in mathematics education must lean more into the complements. Unless the complementing practices described above are also given power through policy, practice, and content, they will always struggle to compete with the very real power and history of the current SMP. This may require an altogether re-imagining of the SMP and the content standards. Mathematics pedagogy and policy has too long painted with a narrow pallet. Students deserve a math is more about joy, intuition, creativity, and appreciation. They deserve experiences that are Critical and liberating. They deserve to see a full picture of math that both includes them and that they have the power to change. This work can be aided and advanced by first acknowledging that the current and official enumeration of mathematical practice is woefully incomplete. Acknowledgements This post owes a great deal of gratitude and acknowledgment to three works: Rochelle Gutiérrez’s Living Mathematx: Toward a Vision for the Future, Williams Byers’ How Mathematician’s Think, and Ani DiFranco’s No Walls and the Recurring Dream. In addition to the specific citations, the spirit and philosophy behind of those works certainly informed, inspired, and shaped my thinking in ways that are difficult to explicitly cite but must be deeply acknowledged. The ideas here are a mere application or extension of the insights their works revealed. Citations 1 Byers, William. How Mathematicians Think. Princeton (2007) 2 The phrase “appreciate the reasoning of others” and corresponding idea originated in Gutierrez, R. “Living Mathematx: Towards a Vision for the Future.” Philosophy of Mathematics Education Journal. November (2017). 3 O’Neil, Cathy. Weapons of Math Destruction. Crown (2016). 4 Difranco, Ani. No Walls and the Recurring Dream. Viking (2019).
Reason concretely, spatially, and intuitively
Propose inviable and incomplete ideas and appreciate the reasoning of others2
Consider and respond to the impact mathematics has on people
Develop new tools and use them creatively
Abandon precision
Ignore structure and make use of its absence
Find and value uniqueness